Achieving excellence in terms of aristotles nichomachean ethics

Prudence is not, but cleverness is, compatible with incontinence He tells us there are three kinds of good toward which our choices look, the pleasant, the beautiful, and the beneficial or advantageous. On the other hand, Aristotle does not mean to imply that every pleasure should be chosen.

He organizes his material by first studying ethical virtue in general, then moving to a discussion of particular ethical virtues temperance, courage, and so onAchieving excellence in terms of aristotles nichomachean ethics finally completing his survey by considering the intellectual virtues practical wisdom, theoretical wisdom, etc.

For as in the Ancient Olympic Games"it is not the most beautiful or the strongest who are crowned, but those who compete". Our first or childish nature is never eradicated, though, and this is why Aristotle says that our nature is not simple, but also has in it something different that makes our happiness assailable from within, and makes us love change even when it is for the worse.

But it is only in the moral virtues that we possess our primary nature, that in which all our capacities can have their full development.

Aristotle's Ethics

Does such good will exist in all three kinds of friendship, or is it confined to relationships based on virtue? And indeed it would be too absurd to leave what is noblest and fairest to the dispensation of chance. The soul is analyzed into a connected series of capacities: Can no man be called happy during life?

Similarly, in facing situations that arouse anger, a virtuous agent must determine what action if any to take in response to an insult, and although this is not itself a quantitative question, his attempt to answer it properly requires him to have the right degree of concern for his standing as a member of the community.

In Book III, chapter 8, Aristotle refuses to give the name courageous to anyone who acts bravely for the sake of honor, out of shame, from experience that the danger is not as great as it seems, out of spiritedness or anger or the desire for revenge, or from optimism or ignorance.

These in turn can allow the development of a good stable character in which the habits are voluntary, and this in turn gives a chance of achieving eudaimonia. It is understandable that there is a difference between being successful and being morally good.

The latter word, that can be translated as being-at-work, cannot mean mere behavior, however repetitive and constant it may be. The answer according to Aristotle is that it must involve articulate speech logosincluding both being open to persuasion by reasoning, and thinking things through.

If what we know about virtue is only what is said in Books II through V, then our grasp of our ultimate end is radically incomplete, because we still have not studied the intellectual virtue that enables us to reason well in any given situation. He describes a sequence of necessary steps to achieve this: But achieving this supreme condition is inseparable from achieving all the virtues of character, or "moral virtues".

Aristotle says that such cases will need to be discussed later, before the discussion of Justice in Book V, which will also require special discussion. But he cannot present such an argument, because he does not believe it.

The good of a human being must have something to do with being human; and what sets humanity off from other species, giving us the potential to live a better life, is our capacity to guide ourselves by using reason. Amusements will not be absent from a happy life, since everyone needs relaxation, and amusements fill this need.

But we will not dwell on these matters now, for they are sufficiently discussed in the popular treatises. For it seems to me that the physician does not even seek for health in this abstract way, but seeks for the health of man, or rather of some particular man, for it is individuals that he has to heal.

It is partly a confusion between an effect and one of its causes. And it should be noticed that the beautiful is at work not only in the human realm. Because each party benefits the other, it is advantageous to form such friendships. And he explicitly compares the well made work of art to an act that springs from moral virtue.

Aristotle is not recommending that his readers make this intellectual virtue part of their ultimate aim. And for the same reason we may dismiss the Edition: Wilson called them "little geniuses"--they do all the work.

This need not be means-end reasoning in the conventional sense; if, for example, our goal is the just resolution of a conflict, we must determine what constitutes justice in these particular circumstances.

Even so, it may still seem perplexing that these two intellectual virtues, either separately or collectively, should somehow fill a gap in the doctrine of the mean.

He says, not that happiness is virtue, but that it is virtuous activity. We all start out life governed by desires and impulses.

Achieving Excellence in Terms of Aristotle’s Nichomachean Ethics

But it would also be strange to suppose that the dead are not affected at all, even for a limited time, by the fortunes of their posterity. Aristotle says that while all the different things called good do not seem to have the same name by chance, it is perhaps better to "let go for now" because this attempt at precision "would be more at home in another type of philosophic inquiry", and would not seem to be helpful for discussing how particular humans should act, in the same way that doctors do not need to philosophize over the definition of health in order to treat each case.

So far from offering a decision procedure, Aristotle insists that this is something that no ethical theory can do. Why isn't all habituation of the young of this sort?Achieving excellence in terms of Aristotle’s “Nichomachean Ethics” Before actually focusing on the main details of Aristotle’s Argument, we must pay careful attention to the opening remarks he makes in Book I about the nature of his inquiry.

The Nicomachean Ethics (/ in the original Aristotelian senses of these terms. In other words, it is not only a contemplation about good living, because it also aims to create good living. The Good of man is the active exercise of his soul's faculties in conformity with excellence or virtue, or if there be several human excellences or.

I wish gratefully to acknowledge the debt which, in common with all lovers of Aristotle, I owe to Mr. Bywater, both for his edition and for his “Contributions to the Textual Criticism of the Nicomachean Ethics” (Oxford, ).

Aristotle In Nicomachean Ethics Aristotle makes the case for the fulfillment of Eudimonea, the greatest happiness and good that a person can achieve/5(1). Read this Philosophy Essay and over 88, other research documents. Achieving Excellence in Terms of Aristotle’s Nichomachean Ethics. Before actually focusing on the main details of Aristotle's Argument, we must pay.

Aristotle: Ethics. Standard interpretations of Aristotle’s Nichomachean Ethics usually maintain that Aristotle ( B.C.E.) emphasizes the role of habit in conduct. It is commonly thought that virtues, according to Aristotle, are habits and that the good life is a life of mindless routine.

Download
Achieving excellence in terms of aristotles nichomachean ethics
Rated 4/5 based on 73 review